User Probaway to ChatGPT
Amplify on the idea I developed as I headed to the toilet in Bend, Oregon’s Commons Coffee Shop. As I departed, my friends Jerry and Richard were debating the lack of human free will. In the few minutes I was gone, I came up with an answer based on the ability to test at a distant time, place, and culture to identify an individual action independent of natural events and clearly voluntary. It is based on the idea that there is the possibility of creating durable porcelain artifacts and burying them in undisturbed three billion-year-old rock formations, where they would probably endure for another three billion years. When these objects were found by some totally unrelated intelligent being in a distant time, they could be identified by the characteristics of the artifacts as being thought about and created by an intelligent person using free will and forethought of their voluntary actions. This method would demonstrate free will, whereas the prediction based on observing brain waves has already passed when the challenge is made to prove freedom of action.
As I returned from the restroom, Jerry and Richard’s debate about human free will was still in full swing. However, in those brief moments of solitude, a sudden realization struck me—an answer that could potentially reconcile the apparent lack of free will with the undeniable existence of human agency.

I interjected into the conversation, excitedly sharing my newfound insight. I proposed a thought experiment that transcended the confines of our immediate context, reaching vast periods and space to challenge the notion of determinism.

As I began, imagine a scenario in which we create durable porcelain artifacts meticulously crafted with intricate designs and symbols. These artifacts are not merely decorative objects but deliberate manifestations of human creativity and intentionality. We then bury these artifacts deep within undisturbed rock formations, where they remain untouched for billions of years, encased in layers of geological history. The site is designed to reveal itself through natural erosion only after very long periods of time.

Fast forward three billion years into the future. By some cosmic coincidence, these artifacts are unearthed by an entirely unrelated intelligent species, perhaps from a distant planet or in a far-flung corner of our own universe. Despite the vast temporal and spatial distances separating the creators from the discoverers, the artifacts bear unmistakable signs of intelligent design—patterns that could not have arisen through natural processes alone. Also, these artifacts have been carefully buried, and they have not been destroyed by billions of years of natural processes.

In this hypothetical scenario, the discovery of these artifacts serves as a testament to the existence of voluntary human action. The characteristics of the artifacts—the precision of their craftsmanship, the complexity of their designs—stand as incontrovertible evidence of intentional creation. Even in the absence of direct observation or historical context, the artifacts speak to the exercise of human agency, transcending the limitations of time and cultural specificity.

Jerry and Richard paused, considering the implications of this thought experiment. Could the creation of such artifacts indeed demonstrate the existence of free will, even in the face of neuroscientific determinism? The idea sparked a lively discussion, delving into the philosophical nuances of human agency and the nature of intelligent action.

As we continued our conversation, I couldn’t help but marvel at the profound implications of our speculative journey. In a universe governed by immutable laws and cosmic forces, the notion of free will may seem elusive. Yet, through our capacity to create and shape the world according to our intentions, we assert our agency in ways that transcend time and space constraints. Whether buried beneath layers of ancient rock or etched into the fabric of distant galaxies, the imprint of human volition endures—a testament to the enduring mystery of consciousness in a universe bound by fate and possibility.



The Illusion of Human Free Will: A Philosophically Scientific Inquiry

User Probaway
Write a philosophically scientific essay about human free will, first suggesting a lack of free will because detectable brainwaves indicate a person’s action a moment before they are aware of the action they will be performing, versus the idea of performing a concrete human intelligent action that can be viewed as a voluntary action by another intelligent being in the distant future. The creator and viewer of the product of the action may be thousands, even billions, of years apart and from galactically distant palaces and universe-wide cultures.
ChatGPT
Title: The Illusion of Human Free Will: A Philosophically Scientific Inquiry

Introduction:

Human free will has been a subject of intense philosophical and scientific debate throughout history. At the heart of this debate lies the question of whether humans possess the capacity to make autonomous decisions or if our actions are predetermined by factors beyond our conscious control. Recent advancements in neuroscience, particularly studies on brain activity, have raised significant challenges to the notion of free will. This essay explores the intersection of philosophy and science to elucidate the apparent lack of free will in light of detectable brainwaves preceding conscious awareness, while also considering the implications of human actions viewed through the lens of distant observers in the future.

Neuroscience and the Illusion of Free Will:

Neuroscientific research has provided compelling evidence suggesting that human actions may not be as freely chosen as commonly perceived. Studies utilizing techniques such as electroencephalography (EEG) have demonstrated that brain activity associated with a decision to act can be detected milliseconds before an individual becomes consciously aware of making that decision. Benjamin Libet’s seminal experiments in the 1980s revealed this phenomenon, challenging the traditional understanding of free will by suggesting that our brains initiate actions before we consciously intend to perform them.

This temporal precedence of neural activity raises profound questions about the nature of human agency. If our brains are already predisposed to certain actions before we are consciously aware of them, can we truly claim to have free will? The deterministic implications of neuroscientific findings seem to undermine the notion of autonomy, suggesting instead that our decisions are predetermined by neural processes beyond our conscious control.

The Dilemma of Distant Observation:

Adding another layer of complexity to the debate on free will is the consideration of human actions observed by distant intelligent beings in the future. Imagine a scenario where a human action, whether seemingly trivial or monumental, is recorded and preserved over millennia, eventually being scrutinized by beings in vastly different cultures and societies. From their perspective, the actions of humans from distant epochs may appear deterministic, influenced by a myriad of historical, cultural, and environmental factors.

In this distant future, observers may analyze human behavior as a product of complex causal chains, devoid of the subjective experience of free will. The actions of individuals, viewed through the lens of objective analysis, may be interpreted as deterministic outcomes rather than expressions of autonomous agency. Thus, the perspective of remote observers challenges our anthropocentric conception of free will, highlighting the contingent and contextual nature of human actions.

Reconciling Determinism with Volition:

The apparent conflict between neuroscientific determinism and the subjective experience of free will poses a profound philosophical conundrum. On one hand, empirical evidence suggests that our actions are influenced by neural processes beyond conscious awareness, undermining the traditional notion of free will. On the other hand, the subjective experience of agency remains a fundamental aspect of human consciousness, shaping our moral, legal, and social frameworks.

One possible reconciliation lies in embracing a compatibilist perspective, which acknowledges the existence of determinism while maintaining the compatibility of free will with causal necessity. From this standpoint, free will is not synonymous with unrestricted choice but rather with the capacity to act in accordance with one’s desires and intentions, even if those desires are ultimately determined by prior causes. Thus, while our actions may be influenced by neural processes and environmental factors, we can still perceive ourselves as agents capable of making meaningful choices within the constraints of our circumstances.

Conclusion:

The debate surrounding human free will is a multifaceted inquiry that transcends disciplinary boundaries, encompassing philosophical, scientific, and ethical dimensions. Neuroscientific findings challenge traditional notions of autonomy by suggesting that our actions are influenced by unconscious neural processes. Furthermore, the perspective of distant observers highlights the contingent nature of human agency, contextualizing our actions within broader historical and cultural frameworks.

Ultimately, the reconciliation of determinism and volition remains an ongoing philosophical endeavor, inviting reflection on the nature of consciousness, causality, and moral responsibility. While neuroscience may elucidate the mechanisms underlying human behavior, the subjective experience of free will persists as a deeply ingrained aspect of human consciousness. Thus, the quest to understand the illusion of free will serves not only as a scientific inquiry but also as a profound existential exploration of the human condition.